Ana səhifə

The psychology of linguistic form


Yüklə 131.5 Kb.
səhifə2/3
tarix24.06.2016
ölçüsü131.5 Kb.
1   2   3

Sentences

On the surface, a sentence is a linear sequence of words. But in order to extract the intended meaning, the listener or reader must combine the words in just the right way. That much is obvious. What is not obvious is how we do that in real time, as we read or listen to a sentence. Of particular relevance to this chapter are the following questions: Is there a representational level of syntactic form that is distinct from the meaning of a sentence? And if so, exactly how do we extract the implicit structure in a spoken or written sentence as we process it? One can ask similar questions about the process of sentence production: When planning a sentence, is there a planning stage that encodes specifically syntactic form? And if so, how do these representations relate to the sound and meaning of the intended utterance?

For purely practical reasons, there is far more research on extracting the syntactic form during sentence comprehension (a process known as parsing; see PARSING, HUMAN) than on planning the syntactic form of to-be-spoken sentences. Nonetheless, research in both areas has led to substantive advances in our understanding of the psychology of sentence form.

Syntax and semantics. A fundamental claim of GENERATIVE GRAMMARS is that syntax and semantics are clearly distinct. A fundamental claim of COGNITIVE GRAMMARS is that syntax and semantics are so entwined that they cannot be easily separated. This debate among linguists is mirrored by a similar debate among researchers studying language processing. A standard assumption underlying much psycholinguistic work is that a relatively direct mapping exists between the levels of knowledge posited within generative linguistic theories and the cognitive and neural processes underlying comprehension (Bock and Kroch 1989). Distinct language-specific processes are thought to interpret a sentence at each level of analysis, and distinct representations are thought to result from these computations. But other theorists, most notably those working in the connectionist framework, deny that this mapping exists (Elman et al. 1996). Instead, the meaning of the sentence is claimed to be derived directly, without an intervening level of syntactic structure.

The initial evidence of separable syntactic and semantic processing streams came from studies of brain-damaged patients suffering from APHASIA, in particular the syndromes known as Broca’s and Wernicke’s aphasia. Broca’s aphasics typically produce slow, labored speech; their speech is generally coherent in meaning but very disordered in terms of sentence structure. Many syntactically important words are omitted (e.g., the, is), as are the inflectional morphemes involved in morphosyntax (e.g., -ing, -ed, -s). Wernicke’s aphasics, by contrast, typically produce fluent, grammatical sentences that tend to be incoherent. Initially, these disorders were assumed to reflect deficits in sensorimotor function; Broca’s aphasia was claimed to result from a motoric deficit, whereas Wernicke’s aphasia was claimed to reflect a sensory deficit. The standard assumptions about aphasia changed in the 1970s, when theorists began to stress the ungrammatical aspects of Broca’s aphasics’ speech; the term “agrammatism” became synonymous with Broca’s aphasia. Particularly important in motivating this shift was evidence that some Broca’s aphasics have a language comprehension problem that mirrors their speech production problems. Specifically, some Broca’s aphasics have trouble understanding syntactically complex sentences (e.g., John was finally kissed by Louise) in which the intended meaning is crucially dependent on syntactic cues – in this case the grammatical words was and by (Caramazza and Zurif 1976). This evidence seemed to rule out a purely motor explanation for the disorder; instead, Broca’s aphasia was viewed as fundamentally a problem constructing syntactic representations, both for production and comprehension. By contrast, Wernicke’s aphasia was assumed to reflect a problem in accessing the meanings of words.

These claims about the nature of the aphasic disorders are still quite influential. Closer consideration, however, raises many questions. “Pure” functional deficits affecting a single linguistically defined function are rare; most patients have a mixture of problems, some of which seem linguistic but others of which seem to involve motor or sensory processing (Alexander 2006). Many of the Broca’s patients who produce agrammatic speech are relatively good at making explicit grammaticality judgments (Linebarger 1983), suggesting that their knowledge of syntax is largely intact. Similarly, it is not uncommon for Broca’s aphasics to speak agrammatically but to have relatively normal comprehension, bringing into question the claim that Broca’s aphasia reflects damage to an abstract “syntax” area used in production and comprehension (Miceli, Mazzuchi, Menn, and Goodglass 1983). Taken together, then, the available evidence from the aphasia literature does not provide compelling evidence for distinct syntactic and semantic processing streams.

Another source of evidence comes from NEUROIMAGING studies of neurologically normal subjects. One useful method involves recording event-related brain potentials (ERPs) from a person’s scalp as they read or listen to sentences. ERPs reflect the summed, simultaneously occurring postsynaptic activity in groups of cortical pyramidal neurons. A particularly fruitful approach has involved the presentation of sentences containing linguistic anomalies. If syntactic and semantic aspects of sentence comprehension are segregated into distinct streams of processing, then syntactic and semantic anomalies might affect the comprehension system in distinct ways. A large body of evidence suggests that syntactic and semantic anomalies do in fact elicit qualitatively distinct ERP effects, and that these effects are characterized by distinct and consistent temporal properties. Semantic anomalies (e.g., The cat will bake the food …) elicit a negative wave that peaks at about 400 ms after the anomalous word appears (the N400 effect) (Kutas & Hillyard 1980). By contrast, syntactic anomalies (e.g., The cat will eating the food …) elicit a large positive wave that onsets at about 500 ms after presentation of the anomalous word and persists for at least half a second (the P600 effect (Osterhout & Holcomb 1992). In some studies, syntactic anomalies have also elicited a negativity over anterior regions of the scalp, with onsets ranging from 100 to 300 ms. These results generalize well across types of anomaly, languages, and various methodological factors. The robustness of the effects seems to indicate that the human brain does in fact honor the distinction between the form and the meaning of a sentence.



Sentence comprehension. Assuming that sentence processing involves distinct syntactic and semantic processing streams, the question arises as to how these streams interact during comprehension. A great deal of evidence indicates that sentence processing is incremental, that is, that each successive word in a sentence is integrated into the preceding sentence material almost immediately. Such a strategy, however, introduces a tremendous amount of AMBIGUITY – that is, uncertainty about the intended syntactic and semantic role of a particular word or phrase. Consider, for example, the sentence fragment The cat scratched . . . . There are actually two ways to parse this fragment. One could parse it as a simple active sentence, in which the cat is playing the syntactic role of subject of the verb scratched, and the semantic role of the entity doing the scratching (as in The cat scratched the ratty old sofa). Or one could parse it as a more complex relative clause structure, in which the verb scratched is the start of a second, embedded clause, and the cat is the entity being scratched, rather than the one doing the scratching (as in The cat scratched by the raccoon was taken to the pet hospital). The ambiguity is resolved once the disambiguating information (the ratty sofa or by the raccoon) is encountered downstream, but that provides little help for a parser that assigns roles to words as soon as they are encountered.

How does an incremental sentence processing system handle such ambiguities? An early answer to this question was provided by the garden-path (or modular) parsing models developed in the1980s. The primary claim was that the initial parse of the sentence is controlled entirely by the syntactic cues in the sentence (Ferreira

and Clifton 1986). As words arrive in the linguistic input, they are rapidly organized into a structural analysis by a process that is not influenced by semantic knowledge. The output of this syntactic process then guides semantic interpretation. This model can be contrasted with interactive models, in which a wide variety of information (e.g., semantics and conceptual/world knowledge) influences the earliest stages of sentence parsing. Initial results of numerous studies (mostly involving the measurement of subjects’ eye movements as they read sentences) indicated that readers tend to read straight through syntactically simple sentences such as The cat scratched the ratty old sofa but experience longer eye fixations and more eye regressions when they encountered by the raccoon in the more complex sentences. When confronted with syntactic uncertainty, readers seemed to immediately choose the simplest syntactic representation available (Frazier 1987). When this analysis turned out to be an erroneous choice (that is, when the disambiguating material in the sentence required a more complex structure), longer eye fixations and more regressions occurred as they reader attempted to “reanalyze” the sentence.

A stronger test of the garden-path model, however, requires examining situations in which the semantic cues in the sentence are clearly consistent with a syntactically complex parsing alternative. A truly modular, syntax-driven parser would be unaffected by the semantic cues in the sentence. Consider, for example, the sentence fragment The sofa scratched . . . . Sofas are soft and inanimate and therefore unlikely to scratch anything. Consequently, the semantic cues in the fragment favor the more complex relative clause analysis, in which the sofa is the entity being scratched (as in The sofa scratched by the cat was given to Goodwill). Initial results seemed to suggest that the semantic cues had no effect on the initial parse of the sentence; readers seemed to build the syntactically simplest analysis possible, even when it was inconsistent with the available semantic information. Such evidence led to the hypothesis that the language processor is comprised of a number of autonomously functioning components, each of which corresponds to a level of linguistic analysis (Ferreira and Clifton 1986). The syntactic component was presumed to function independently of the other components.

The modular syntax-first model has been increasingly challenged, most notably by advocates of constraint-satisfaction models (Trueswell and Tanenhaus 1994). These models propose that all sources of relevant information (including statistical, semantic and real-world information) simultaneously and rapidly influence the actions of the parser. Hence, the implausibility of a sofa scratching something is predicted to cause the parser to initially attempt the syntactically more complex relative clause analysis. Consistent with this claim, numerous studies have subsequently demonstrated compelling influences of semantics and world knowledge on the parser’s response to syntactic ambiguity (Trueswell et al. 1994).

There is, however, a fundamental assumption underlying most of the syntactic ambiguity research (regardless of theoretical perspective): that syntax always controls combinatory processing when the syntactic cues are unambiguous. Recently, this assumption has also been challenged. The challenge centers on the nature of THEMATIC ROLES, which help to define the types of arguments licensed by a particular verb (McRae et al. 1997; Trueswell and Tanenhaus 1994). Exactly what is meant by “thematic role” varies widely, especially with respect to how much semantic and conceptual content it is assumed to hold (McRae et al. 1997). For most “syntax-first” proponents, a thematic role is limited to a few syntactically relevant “selectional restrictions”, such as animacy (Chomsky 1965); thematic roles are treated as (largely meaningless) slots to be filled by syntactically appropriate fillers. A second view is that there is a limited number of thematic roles (agent, theme, benefactor, and so on), and that a verb selects a subset of these (Fillmore 1968). Although this approach attributes a richer semantics to thematic roles, the required generalizations across large classes of verbs obscure many subtleties in the meaning and usage of these verbs.

Both of these conceptions of thematic roles exclude knowledge that people possess concerning who tends to do what to whom in particular situations. McRae and others have proposed a third view of thematic roles that dramatically expands their semantic scope: thematic roles are claimed to be rich, verb-specific concepts that reflect a person’s collective experience with particular actions and objects (McRae et al. 1997). These rich representations are claimed to be stored as a set of features that define gradients of typicality (“situation SCHEMAS”), and to comprise a large part of each verb’s meaning. One implication is that this rich knowledge will become immediately available once a verb’s meaning has been retrieved from memory. As a consequence, the plausibility of a particular word combination need not be evaluated by means of a potentially complex inferential process, but rather can be evaluated immediately in the context of the verb’s meaning. One might therefore predict that semantic and conceptual knowledge of events will have profound and immediate effects on how words are combined during sentence processing. McRae and others have provided evidence consistent with these claims, including semantic influences on syntactic ambiguity resolution.

The most compelling evidence against the absolute primacy of syntax, however, would be evidence that semantic and conceptual knowledge can “take control” of sentence processing even when opposed by contradicting and unambiguous syntactic cues. Recent work by Ferreira (2003) suggests that this might happen on some occasions. Ferreira reported that when plausible sentences (e.g., The mouse ate the cheese) were passivized to form implausible sentences (e.g., The mouse was eaten by the cheese), participants tended to name the wrong entity as “do-er” or “acted-on”, as if coercing the sentences to be plausible. However, the processing implications of these results are uncertain, due to the use of post-sentence ruminative responses, which do not indicate whether semantic influences reflect the listeners’ initial responses to the input or some later aspect of processing.

Researchers have also begun to explore the influence of semantic and conceptual knowledge on the on-line processing of syntactically unambiguous sentences. An illustrative example is a recent ERP study by Kim and Osterhout (2005). The stimuli in this study were anomalous sentences that began with a active structure, for example, The mysterious crime was solving . . .. . The syntactic cues in the sentence require that the noun crime be the Agent of the verb solving. If syntax drives sentence processing, then the verb solving would be perceived to be semantically anomalous, as crime is a poor Agent for the verb solve, and therefore should elicit an N400 effect. However, although crime is a poor Agent, it is an excellent Theme (as in solved the crime).  The Theme role can be accommodated simply by changing the inflectional morpheme at the end of the verb to a passive form ("The mysterious crime was solved . . ."). Therefore, if meaning drives sentence processing in this situation, then the verb solving would be perceived to be in the wrong syntactic form (-ing instead of –ed), and should therefore elicit a P600 effect. Kim and Osterhout observed that verbs like solving elicited a P600 effect, showing that a strong “semantic attraction” between a predicate and an argument can determine how words are combined, even when the semantic attraction contradicts

unambiguous syntactic cues. Conversely, in anomalous sentences with an identical structure but with no semantic attraction between the subject noun and the verb (e.g., The envelope was devouring . . .”), the critical verb elicited an N400 effect rather than a P600 effect. These results demonstrate that semantics, rather than syntax, can “drive” word combination during sentence comprehension.



Sentence production. Generating a sentence requires the rapid construction of novel combinations of linguistic units, involves multiple levels of analysis, and is constrained by a variety of rules (about word order, the formation of complex words, word pronunciation, etc). Errors are a natural consequence of these complexities (Dell 1995). Because they tend to be highly systematic, speech errors have provided much of the data upon which current models of sentence production are based. For example, word exchanges tend to obey a syntactic category rule, in that the exchanged words are from the same syntactic category (for example, two nouns have exchanged in the utterance Stop hitting your brick against a head wall). The systematicity of speech errors suggests that regularities described in theories of linguistic form also play a role in the speech planning process.

The dominant model of sentence production is based on speech error data (Dell 1995; Garrett 1975; Levelt 1989). According to this model, the process of preparing to speak a sentence involves three stages of planning: conceptualization, formulation, and articulation, in that order. During the conceptualization stage, the speaker decides what thought to express, and how to order the relevant concepts sequentially. The formulation stage begins with the selection of a syntactic frame to encode the thought; the frame contains slots that act as place holders for concepts and, eventually, specific words. The phonological string is translated into a string of phonological features, which then drive the motor plan manifested in articulation.

This model therefore posits the existence of representations of syntactic structure that are distinct from the representations of meaning and sound. Other evidence in support of this view comes from the phenomenon of syntactic priming: having heard or produced a particular syntactic structure, a person is more likely to produce sentences using the same syntactic structure (Bock 1986). Syntactic priming occurs independently of sentence meaning, suggesting that the syntactic frames are independent forms of representation that are quite distinct from meaning.
Conclusions

Collectively, the evidence reviewed above indicates that psychologically relevant representations of linguistic form exist at all levels of language, from sounds to sentences. At each level, units of linguistic form are combined in systematic ways to form larger units of representation. For the most part, these representations seem to be abstract; that is, they are distinct from the motor movements, sensory experiences, and episodic memories associated with particular utterances. However, it is also clear that more holistic (that is, non-decompositional) representations of linguistic form, some of which are rooted in specific episodic memories, also play a role in language processing.

It also seems to be true that linguistic forms (e.g., the morphological structure of a word or the syntactic structure of a sentence) are dissociable from the meanings they convey. At the same time, semantic and conceptual knowledge can strongly influence the processing of linguistic forms, as exemplified by semantic transparency effects on word decomposition and thematic role effects on sentence parsing.

These conclusions represent substantive progress in our understanding of linguistic form and the role it plays in language processing. Nonetheless, answers to some of the most basic questions remain contentiously debated, such as the precise nature of the “rules” of combination, the relative roles of compositional and holistic representations, and the pervasiveness of interactions between meaning and form.


References

Alexander, M. P. 2006. “Aphasia I: Clinical and anatomical issues.” In Patient-Based Approaches to Cognitive Neuroscience (2nd ed.), ed. M. J. Farah and T. E. Feinberg, 165-182. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Allen, Mark and William Badecker. 1999. Stem homograph inhibition and stem allomorphy: Representing and processing inflected forms in a multilevel lexical system. Journal of Memory and Language 41:105-123.

Allen, Mark D. 2005. The preservation of verb subcategory knowledge in a spoken language comprehension deficit. Brain and Language 95: 255-264.

Allport, D.A. and E. Funnell. 1981. Components of the mental lexicon. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B 295: 397-410.

Anderson, Stephen R.1985. Phonology in the Twentieth Century: Theories of rules and Theories of Representations. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

Bell, Alexander M. 1867. Visible Speech: The Science of Universal Alphabetics. London: Simpkin, Marshal.

Bloomfield, Leonard. 1933. Language. New York: H. Holt & Co.

Bock, J. K., & Anthony S. Kroch. 1989. “The isolability of syntactic processing.” In Linguistic structure in language processing, ed.. G. N. Carlson and M. K. Tanenhaus, 157-196 Boston: Kluwer Academic.

Brentari, Dianne. 1998. A Prosody Model of Sign Language Phonology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Browman, Catherine P. and Louis Goldstein.1990. Gestural specification using dynamically-defined articulatory structures. Journal of Phonetics 18: 299-320.

Bybee, Joan. 1988. “Morphology as lexical organization.” In Theoretical morphology: Approaches in modern linguistics, ed. M. Hammond & M. Noonan, 119-141. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.

Byrd, Dani and Elliot Saltzman. 2003.The elastic phrase: Modeling the dynamics of boundary-adjacent lengthening, Journal of Phonetics 31: 149–180.

Caplan, David. 1995. Issues arising in contemporary studies of disorders of syntactic processing in sentence comprehension in agrammatic patients. Brain and Language 50: 325-338

Caramazza, Alfonzo and Edgar Zuriff. 1976. Dissociations of algorithmic and heuristic processes in language comprehension: Evidence from aphasia. Brain and Language 3: 572-582.

Chistovich, Ludmilla A. 1960. Classification of rapidly repeated speech sounds. Akustichneskii Zhurnal: 6: 392-398.

Chomsky, Noam. 1957. Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton.

Chomsky, N. 1965. Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA:MIT Press.

Delattre, Pierre and Donald Freeman. 1968. A dialect study of American R's by x-ray motion picture. Linguistics 44: 29-68.

Delattre, Pierre C., Avin M. Liberman, and Franklin S.Cooper. 1955. Acoustic loci and transitional cues for consonants. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 27: 769-773.

Dell, Gary S. 1995. Speaking and misspeaking. In An Invitation to Cognitive Science: Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Draper, M., P. Ladefoged, and D. Whitteridge. 1959. Respiratory muscles in speech. Journal of Speech and Hearing Research 2: 16-27.

1   2   3


Verilənlər bazası müəlliflik hüququ ilə müdafiə olunur ©atelim.com 2016
rəhbərliyinə müraciət