Ana səhifə

Strategies Identify elements and match them to facts


Yüklə 276 Kb.
səhifə3/4
tarix27.06.2016
ölçüsü276 Kb.
1   2   3   4

Evidence of due careNOT enough for a directed verdict; will still go to jury

  • Rebuttal of res ipsa requirements - ∆ can get direct verdict of no other prima facie case



    Causation


    1. Causation In FACT

      1. Even if there was duty and breach, Π must show that the breach was a “but for” cause of his injury; if ∆ had not acted negligently, Π’s injuries wouldn’t have resulted.

        1. No causation in not throwing life preserver if Π wouldn’t have been saved anyway.

        2. There is still “but for” causation when there are multiple tortfeasors

      2. Less than 50% chance Π would’ve been saved: (life saving cases);

        1. Minority rule allows for discounted recovery.

        2. “If D’s conduct increases risk of harm, and P suffers injury of the type that would have been caused by that harm, then it goes to the jury”

        3. Beswick – (corrupt 911 operator case). Must simply prove more likely than not (51% chance) that there would have been a 34% chance of survival if ∆ was not negligent.

        4. Proportional damages - ∆ should only pay for expected value of non-negligent action. Example: 3 sailors go overboard and precaution would’ve enabled ∆ to save one – pay 1/3 of each life.

        5. Tension between risk compensation and injury compensation

        6. Med/mal rule  compensate patient for chances of survival w/o negligence. Over 100 case, doctor (theoretically) will be liable for all lives lost.

          1. Rule justified by systematic defect. If there was a 37.5% chance of survival with added procedure, doctors will never pay for failing to perform.

          2. Minority Rule  most argue unfair for doctors to have to cover 100% of loss in cases where probability of survival was 51%.

      3. Concurrent causes: Can meet “cause in fact” inquiry, but not the “but for” cause inquiry – two evens occur simultaneously, one of which is sufficient to cause damage (e.g. two fires joining). Each is deemed a cuase in fact.

      4. Counterfactual Inquiry: Difficulty with finding cause in fact is that it requires construction of a fictional world without the cause present. This can sometimes lead to difficult evidentiary burdens.




    1. Multiple Tortfeasors  Joint and Several Liability

      1. Theoretical justification for liability of multiple ∆’s

        1. Each D owed a duty to P

        2. Each D breached that duty to P

        3. Each D was a substantial factor, or contributed to the injury suffered by P

      2. Joint Liability  both D’s are liable, join in paying damages.

      3. Several liability  In principle, doesn’t require ∆ to pay for full damages. D may only be liable for his share of damages.

      4. Joint and several liability  If more than one person is in proximate cuase of Π’s harms, and harm is indivisible, each ∆ is liable for entire harm. can sue either all or one of defendants. Can’t get over 100% compensation (one can pay all damages, or multiple D’s can split damages).

        1. Π cannot recover twice – entitled to “single satisfaction

        2. If harms are divisible, they will be apportioned amongst the tortfeasors

      5. Apportionment

        1. Action in concert: ∆’s acting in concert each liabile for injuries directly caused by other (no apportionment)  e.g. drag racers

        2. Successive injuries separated by substantial periods of time leads to apportionment.

        3. Overlapping: ∆ who caused initial harm is liable for whole thing; ∆ who caused later harm is only liable for amount by which he worsened harm; e.g. ∆1 negligently breaks Π’s arm; ∆2 negligently sets it so it has to be amputated. ∆ 1 liable for everything; ∆2 liable for difference between broken and amputated arm.

        4. Death and fire are paradigmatic indivisible harms

      6. Contribution If one ∆ pays more than his pro rata share, the other can obtain partial reimbursement. Usually limited to unintentional torts; Contribution ∆ must be liable; split about what to do if D1 settles and D2 sue for contribution after subsequent judgment.

      7. Action for indemnity D1 sues and D2 covers D1 in full

      8. Joint and severable liability allocates risk that one D is judgment-proof to the other D’s instead of allocating risk to Π

        1. Allocating risk of insolvency to culpable D, rather than P who suffered injury

        2. Fair to impose liability on ∆; w/o his negligence, there wouldn’t have been injury.




    1. Market Share Liability

      1. Alternative Liability  Multiple Fault

        1. If one of two ∆’s injured Π, but can’t prove which particular ∆ caused the harm; ∆’s must split the damages equally.

        2. Each ∆ pays share of damages relative to his membership in group

        3. Requires Joinder of all potential ∆s

        4. Reconceptualize identity of ∆ – must prove (51%) that group caused injury

        5. Burden shifts to each to show that others caused harm

        6. In Summers, man was negligently shot, but impossible to prove which ∆ actually hit him – they split damages.




      1. Market Share theory Products liability (prescription drugs)

        1. Π cannot prove which of 3 or more producers of defective products caused his injury

        2. Can show that each of ∆s made defective product

        3. Court will assign liability for % of injuries proportional to ∆’s % of market sales of product at time of injury.

        4. Courts split on exculpation by proving that ∆ did not make particular item in question (e.g. Π’s pharmacy used another brand)

        5. Court use national market share to determine share of liability

        6. NOT JOINT Don’t need all tortfeasors to take action

        7. NOT joint-and-several liability Π can only collect from any one ∆ that ∆’s share

        8. Socially value cuts against market share; e.g. courts likely to reject in case of vaccine

        9. Controversial Only accepted in half the jurisdictions in which it’s been argued. Still, if you don’t accept this analysis, then there must be some other justification for Summers.




    1. Vicarious liability

      1. Elements:

        1. Principal – agent relationship: Employer/employee; master/servant

        2. Agent acting for w/in scope of enterprise (intent to further employer’s business interest); or

        3. Risk characteristic of business enterprise

      2. Liability for reasonably foreseeable detours (5 min trip to buy cigarettes)

      3. Liable for forbidden acts done in furtherance of employment

      4. NOT liable for intentional acts done for personal motives

      5. Theory: Since agent can bind principal by acts, then principal ought to be bound by torts committed by agents

      6. Early courts thought exclusively in terms of agency law

        1. as long as agent was actingw/in scope of agency

        2. Had to be operating for benefit of employer

      7. Narrow view rejected in Bushey

        1. drunken sailor comes back to Brooklyn from drinking in Manhattan and damages dry dock

        2. Clearly sailor was not acting for benefit of US gov’t, nor to further any purpose

      8. Characteristic risk  What does this mean?

        1. Example: military leave. Relief of job stress leads to excess drinking.

      9. Employee Compensation perspective: There are inherent risks of tortuous action in job (e.g. road rage for FedEx driver. Employer covers liability as compensation (instead of paying employees more money)

      10. Vicariously liable employer can sue employee for contribution or indemnity

        1. Any vicariously liable principle has an action against agent that causes torts

        2. In practice action is rarely exercised Empirical proof of claim that employees would want additional compensation if they were to be held liable.


    Proximate Cause


    1. Policy Decision

      1. Tortious actions have far-reaching and improbable consequences

      2. Proximate cause says that ∆ should NOT be responsible for all causes that are unforeseeable; e.g.∆ hits car – happens to be full of dynamite, which causes explosion - nurse 10 blocks away drops a baby. ∆ not liable to baby

      3. Can be multiple proximate causes




    1. Directness Test

      1. Indirect cause it NOT the proximate cause of the injury

      2. Is there a difference between directness and proximity test?

      3. Differ for risks that are direct results but nor foreseeability.

      4. Polemus Cause

        1. FACTS: Plank being raised by a winch falls. Boat full of benzene. Spark from fall starts explosion and ship burns

        2. Cause of fire is direct. Plank falling causes spark that starts fire

        3. But unforeseeable that plank falling would cause a spark and start a fire

        4. Conduct was unreasonable because of a certain kind of risk, but not the risk of what happened




    1. Foreseeability Test

      1. Consequences must be foreseeable.

        1. If risk is not of the type that makes conduct negligent, then there is no liability

        2. Risk is outside duty of ∆; It’s an unforeseeable risk – breach not proximate cause.

        3. To impose liability for unforeseeable risks is out of line with duty (B


      2. Wagon Mound: Oil spill is ignited by workers repairing another boat in the harbor using torches. Spilling oil was tortuous conduct. Held that burning dock was not foreseeable; overturned Polemus

      3. Union Pump Defective pump causes fire. Fire is put out, but P slips and falls afterwards because of water on the floor. Most helpful way to conceptualize  we don’t want fires because people could get hurt putting the out. Outer bounds: but still engaged in putting gout

      4. Problem: Foreseeability is already a test for duty. Isn’t this redundant. Difference is consequences of inquiry  duty question goes to judge; causation goes to jury.




    1. Foreseeable Plaintiff Palsgraff

      1. ∆ is only liabile for injury to foreseeable plaintiff.

      2. Geistfeld: Look at risk that rendered the conduct negligent – different than risk that caused harm to Mrs. P.

        1. No connection to risk that made the conduct negligent and risk that caused in jury

        2. No different than can of nitroglycerin falling on somebody’s foot, or snow swirl case.

      3. Opinions framed in terms of duty: Cardozo (majority) says this is a case about foreseeable victim; Andrews (dissent) says this is about universal duty – RR had a duty to Π as a customer.

      4. Common interpretation  Cordozo gets right result, but it’s about proximate cause/foreseeability.

      5. Geistfeld  politics: does question go before judge or jury?




    1. Risk Rule

      1. Once you push the risk rule, it’s hard to understand difference between directness test and foreseeability test.

      2. Easier than counterfactual inquiry required for cause in fact inquiry

      3. Is the type of risk the duty to take reasonable precaution was meant to prevent?

      4. No liability if there’s mismatch between kind of risk and actual injury.

      5. Example #1: Mislabeled can of poison case in P’s kitchen explodes because it’s near a stove.

        1. Cause in fact: Same accident would have happened if properly labeled can of poison was left above the stove.

        2. ∆ shouldn’t be liable for mislabeling

      6. Example #2: Can of nitroglycerin on edge of table that falls off and breaks Π’s foot.

        1. Cause in fact: It would not have been negligent to put a heavy can on the edge of a table. Negligent conduct isn’t a cause of the injury.

        2. Risk of explosion is the main concern

      7. Still liable if injury is general class of harms but it occurred in an unusual manner:

        1. E.g. If ∆ gives pistol to child X, and X drops it. He is liable to Π who is hit by shot (getting shot is type of risk), despite that it occurred in strange manner. ∆ is not liable to Y whose foot was broken because child dropped pistol on it.

        2. See Kinsman  flooding of town was a concern when ship got loose, despite strange manner in which scenario played out

    2. Intervening cause 

      1. Force which takes effect after ∆’s negligence and contributes to producing Π’s injury

      2. not always clear how intervening cause differs from “direct cause”

        1. If intervening cause if foreseeable, D is liable

      3. superseding cause”  intervening cuase that is sufficient to prevent ∆ from being negligent. Unforeseeable intervening cause.

        1. Often an unforeseeable intervention with unforeseeable results

        2. Extraordinary Act of Nature

      4. A third person’s criminal or negligent behavior may be considered foreseeable and might not exonerate ∆ (e.g. foreseeable that care will be stolen if you leave keys in ignition

      5. Natural responses are often NOT superseding causes

        1. Escape

        2. Rescue – may be liable to rescuer or rescued as long as rescue was not performed in a grossly careless manner.

        3. Aggravation of injury from medical treatment: liable unless gross mistreatment

      6. Liable for unforeseeable intervention with foreseeable result.

    Defenses to Negligence
    Contributory Negligence  Comparative Fault


    1. Contributory negligence

      1. Originally Common Law Denied Remedy to any Π who was found to have contributed to the injury through his own negligent behavior

      2. Complete defense

      3. Conceptually: Single tortuous cause of injury

      4. Smith v. Smith – wood pile negligently left in middle of road. No liability because Π was driving carelessly




    1. Analysis of Multiple causes

      1. matrix

        1. Dn + Pn = Injury

        2. Dn + Prc = No Injury

        3. Drc + Pn = No Injury

        4. Drc + Prc = No injury

      2. SymmetryAny argument D could make, P could make in reverse

        1. ∆ says consider rows three and four

        2. Π says consider rows 2 and 4

        3. To single out the P as being the cause would be unfair, because D caused it to the same degree

        4. That unfairness led to establishment of comparatively responsibility




    1. Last Clear Chance

      1. Early answer to contributory negligence

      2. If D has last clear chance, then he is responsible

      3. D comes upon P, knows that P was contributory negligent, D has last clear chance to avoid accident

      4. temporal relation of actions

        1. Actors must make an assumptions about what other actors are doing.

        2. Ordinarily, when decisions are made, neither side knows what the other is doing

        3. In last clear chance, one side knows what the other party has already done.

        4. Since ∆ cannot say he thought Π was acting cautiously; e.g. conductor saw pedestrian on the railroad tracks

      5. Last Clear chance is no longer majority rule  only needed in jurisdictions that still have contributory negligence.




    1. Comparative responsibility

      1. Unfairness results from Cont. Neg. - Recognizes that last clear chance is just an exception

      2. Impure comparative responsibility Once P is over 50% responsible, there is no recovery at all

      3. Pure approach Even is P is 99% at fault, can still recover

      4. Equal division rule each party pays 50%; Easy rule to apply

      5. Comparative fault is a misnomer: We’re not comparing fault; we’re comparing responsibility (degree of risk creation) – both are at fault.

      6. Problem: no concrete formula to apportion damages. How do you divide it up?

      7. Theory: B >PL  ∆ assumes risk because he is getting some type of subjective benefit




    1. Assumption of Risk

      1. Elements

        1. Knowledge of risk

        2. Voluntary choice to face it

      2. Analysis: Row three gets knocked out. Think about case in terms of Row 1 and Row 2.

      3. Analogous to last clear chance doctrine - Asymmetry of knowledge

        1. ∆’s knowledge of Π’s plight in last clear chance

        2. Π’s knowledge of what ∆ is doing in assumption of risk

      4. Contracts: Assumption of risk must be implied by circumstances surrounding contract (Π must have knowledge of risk)

      5. Primary vs. Secondary Implied Assumption of Risk

        1. Primary: get in car knowing that the brakes don’t work well  bars recovery

        2. Secondary: I’m in car already, and I find out breaks don’t work. I can get out w/o endangering self, but I stay in  not a defense in comparative responsibility jurisdiction

          1. voluntary informed choice

          2. D already breached duty

        3. SAR Shows that courts want to throw this all into comparative fault, but in PAR cases, they just can’t get there

        4. Not a defensible distinction, but it’s still invoked.

      6. Policy Argument  no assumption of risk creates uniformity of precaution which is socially undesireable (e.g. no Black Diamonds).

        1. Allow reasonable actors to make informed decisions




    1. Charitable Immunity

      1. Quid pro quo rationale:

        1. non-profit must be giving me a gift

        2. quid pro quo is they get off from neg liability

      2. Faulty Rationale:

        1. Non-profits benefit society.

        2. Liability causes bankruptcy and denies benefit to society

        3. Discourages charitable activity

        4. How does this differ from private organizations w/ socially valuable activities?

        5. Courts end up abolishing immunity (hard to justify)

      1. Analog to duty of rescue

        1. Must rescue w/ reasonable care (if you have no duty)

        2. Jurisdictions are hesitant to impose negligence liability (e.g. doctor is conferring gift on person in need) - threat of liability will deter people from rescuing

        3. Likewise, we are worried that negligence will deter charitable acts

      1. relief from ordinary negligence (not gross negligence, intentional torts)

      2. Abolished in over 30 states; other cut back on doctrine (e.g. abolished for charity hospitals)




    1. Family Immunity

      1. Two common Law immunities: between husband and wife (Interspousal) and parent child. Neither side can bring tort action against the other.

      2. Spousal abolished in over half of states; other states partially abolished (e.g. not applicable for personal injury)

      3. Parent Child abolished in many (thought not most) states



    1. Sovereign (government) Immunity

      1. Reasoning:

        1. don’t want court to have power over governmental officials

        2. In effect common law court would determine policy decisions by exec officials and legislators

      2. Discretionary Function No liability for high level policy-making decisions

      3. Priprietary function no immunity for revenue generating function such as hospital, airporst

      4. Acting w/in scope of duty: Legislators and judges usually get broad immunity

      5. Must be waived through statute

      6. Routinely waived to extent that conduct was ordinary conduct

        1. Question: When is conduct legislative or executive, and when is it “ordinary conduct?” “discretionary choices” are the hard cases

      7. Questions:

        1. Was gov’t actor involved in discretionary function (policy judgment)?

        2. Was gov’t actor involved in other function?

      8. Arguments for D focus on liability impact on policy decisions

        1. courts are more prone to find sovereign immunity

        2. Determine argument by understanding reason for immunity



    Damages


    1. Evidentiary standard

      1. Must show with reasonably available evidence that physical injury caused the damages in question

      2. Foreseeability and directness are irrelevant
  • 1   2   3   4


    Verilənlər bazası müəlliflik hüququ ilə müdafiə olunur ©atelim.com 2016
    rəhbərliyinə müraciət